Newcomb’s Problem and Order in Game Theory

clevercomputer

I’ve read a lot of LessWrong recently, and I learned about a particular paradox known as Newcomb’s problem. In the problem, an alien superintelligence called Omega presents you with a problem. He gives you two boxes, box A and box B. He puts $1000 in box A and either $0 or $1,000,000 in box B. You can then choose whether to take both boxes or just box B, but the catch is that Omega will only put $1,000,000 in B if he predicts that you will only take B. And given that Omega is able to perfectly predict the future, everyone who chooses only B will get $1,000,000 while everyone who chooses both will get $1000.

The maddening thing about this problem is that, as you sit puzzling over whether to take both boxes, the monetary amounts have already been decided and placed in the boxes. There’s either $1000 or $1,001,000 sitting in front of you, and so it would seem that taking both would be weakly better than taking only one. And yet, everyone who takes only one gets $999,000 more than everyone who takes both. How could it be that the “right” answer gives less money than the “wrong” answer?

Before I return to what I think is the right answer to this problem, I’d like to talk a bit about game theory. In game theory, we distinguish between simultaneous games and sequential games. Simultaneous games are games where each player makes his choices without knowledge of the other player’s choice. The choices could be literally simultaneous, as in rock-paper-scissors, or they could be occurring at different times. For instance, in the board game Diplomacy, all players have a fifteen minute window during which they can write their moves. If France writes his moves after five minutes but Germany takes the whole fifteen, the game is still simultaneous because France’s moves remain hidden to Germany while he is deciding his move.

My point is that it’s knowledge, not the literal passage of time, that determines the order of play in a strategic setting. In Newcomb’s problem, Omega literally makes the first move in deciding how much money to put in the boxes. However, Omega’s ability to predict the future means he decides with knowledge of the box that you will choose. Thus, Omega is the second mover from a strategic perspective. Omega knows what you will do before you do, and you don’t know what Omega has done until after you do it, because you can’t see the contents of the boxes.

All this is to say that choosing box B is the right answer from a game theory perspective. You should play as if Omega hasn’t decided yet how much money to put in the box, because from the perspective of your own knowledge, he hasn’t.

The post Newcomb’s Problem and Order in Game Theory appeared first on The Economics Detective.

The Trolley Car Approach to Public Policy

trolley

Scott Alexander has an article at Slate Star Codex discussing the use of edge cases in moral philosophy:

There’s a tradition at least as old as Kant of investigating philosophical dilemmas by appealing to our intuitions about extreme cases. Kant, remember, proposed that it was always wrong to lie. A contemporary of his, Benjamin Constant, made the following objection: suppose a murderer is at the door and wants to know where your friend is so he can murder her. If you say nothing, the murderer will get angry and kill you; if you tell the truth he will find and kill your friend; if you lie, he will go on a wild goose chase and give you time to call the police. Lying doesn’t sound so immoral now, does it?

This is a great way of doing philosophy, but reading it, I realized I had heard it before. I’ve heard this sort of argument in the context of policy debates.

Here’s a particularly striking example (h/t to Jason Brennan):

abolish_capitalism

Unlike the case of the door-to-door murderer, which is a deliberately fanciful way of examining a broader moral truth, this is a policy proposal made on the basis of a fanciful scenario. The argumentation goes like this:

  1. In an unlikely scenario, economic system A would allow bad outcome X
  2. Therefore, abolish A (and substitute it with another system, such as B)

There are a lot of errors packed into this line of thinking. What if bad outcome X happens under both systems? What if changing systems just substitutes bad outcome Y for X? What this fails to do is compare the relevant alternatives. Is the implicit claim that under socialism, nobody would ever starve? Millions of Soviet citizens beg to differ.

Here’s one I made in response:

Random Violence

The reasoning is essentially the same: I can think of an unlikely scenario in which a policy (illegal violence) would allow a terrible outcome to occur (the next Hitler). Is a future dictator walking around more fanciful than the scenario above? It’s hard to say.

In the first scenario, we have a person who can’t get the income to buy food, so his only recourse is to steal. This person can’t find a job despite the many opportunities present in a capitalist system. He can’t get charity or welfare (if it exists). And yet he is able-bodied and mentally sound enough to successfully break into a warehouse. Seems pretty unlikely. In the second, we have a young Hitler narrowly avoiding a sniper’s bullet.

Here are the questions we should ask ourselves: Would more people starve under capitalism or socialism? Would more people suffer violent deaths under legal random violence or under illegal random violence?

Under capitalism, assuming a pure free market with no welfare state and no private charity (!), people who didn’t have enough money would starve. However, capitalist incentives lead people to produce vast quantities of food and bring them to consumers at minimal cost. Where did you think the warehouses came from? If you can mow someone’s lawn for $5, you can buy five cans of beans, which will feed you for a few days in a stretch. If you can mow five lawns, you can eat much more than just beans.

Under socialism, the central authority needs to coordinate the entire production and distribution of food. This is no easy task. The Soviet Union suffered famines every decade or so. And even when there wasn’t a famine, store shelves wouldn’t have anything near the level of selection we enjoy under capitalism.  Soviet officials were supposed to have fallen to their knees and wept upon entering ordinary American grocery stores. That Americans took for granted what their smartest planners spent half a century failing to achieve was a shocking revelation.

So do more people starve under capitalism or under socialism? Capitalism wins this one, unambiguously, in both theory and practice. Do more people die in a world where random shootings are legal? Clearly yes. And yet if we restrict our attention to a single fanciful scenario, we can come to the opposite conclusion. This is neither surprising nor relevant.

Applying the Argument to Socialized Medicine

The place where I find people are most prone to this sort of reasoning is medical care. “If Canada didn’t have socialized health care, people who got sick would get impoverished or die!” Well, no. Private insurance can insure people against idiosyncratic risks without socialization. “But what if some people don’t think to buy insurance and get sick?” Yes, that might happen. I could say that people should be responsible for managing their own lives, and buying health insurance is part of that. If that doesn’t satisfy you, I could say that loads of people feel just the way you do about people being ruined by illness, probably enough to crowd-fund treatments for such people without government intervention.

But if you must have a government solution, and it must yield absolute certainty that no uninsured person be ruined by an unexpected illness, then let the government create a bare-bones health insurance plan, the cost of which can be refunded to everyone who buys private insurance.

Socialization goes way beyond solving the “uninsured people might get sick and die” problem and creates a whole load of problems of its own. It involves the government haphazardly attempting to plan a whole industry, driving up costs through inefficiency and perverse incentives, and rationing care through wait lists.

When limes shot up in price last year, we had rationing. We rationed through prices. People who didn’t want to pay $2/lime didn’t buy limes. When a bunch of Canadians need to see specialists or get MRI scans (which is always), the rationing doesn’t happen through price but through waiting lists. We hear stories every day of people dying on wait lists or suffering from chronic pain for months awaiting surgery. These people would gladly have paid to get immediate treatment, and while their willingness to pay might mean bidding some medical resources away from others less willing to pay, it would also lead capitalist entrepreneurs to invest more resources in the medical sector. More medicine for all!

People want socialized medicine because they don’t want anyone to ever die because they can’t afford treatment. And yet people dying because their treatment was excessively delayed don’t get much attention. It’s hard to understand why. I suppose the former would kill the poor, while the latter is an equal-opportunity killer?

Consequentialism without Cost-Benefit Analysis?

But this whole discussion is wrong-headed in that we haven’t established just how many people would die from each of these causes under each of these systems! When we’re doing moral philosophy, it doesn’t mater if our scenarios actually come to pass. The trolley-car problem can tell us something interesting about our moral intuitions regardless of how often I tie people to trolley car tracks and force you to choose whether to flip a switch to kill some and not others (man, that was a crazy weekend). But the hypothetical uninsured person dying for lack of treatment tells us precisely nothing about policy unless we know just how many people are dying. Is it comparable to the number of people killed by buckets? Or is it more like the number of people killed in car accidents?

Ban Buckets

Without knowing, we can’t do any sort of cost-benefit analysis. But the original arguments (against capitalism and for socialized medicine) were couched in consequentialist terms. Consequentialism without cost-benefit analysis is incoherence.

I can’t help myself, so here’s one last meme:

trolley_meme

The post The Trolley Car Approach to Public Policy appeared first on The Economics Detective.

Income and Wealth Inequality with David R. Henderson

wallet

…or How I Learned to Stop Worrying and Love Inequality.

David R. Henderson is a research fellow at Stanford University’s Hoover Institution, and a professor of economics at the Graduate School of Business and Public Policy, Naval Postgraduate School, in Monterey, California.

Thomas Piketty’s Capital in the 21st Century managed to do something unprecedented among equation-dense economic tomes, it became the #1 selling book on Amazon.com. The book tapped in to a hot topic among politicians and the general public: the high (and possibly rising) wealth and income shares of the top 1%. However, David points out that although the book was a best-seller, it wasn’t actually a best-reader. Amazon logs the sentences people highlight, and the top five most-highlighted sentences in Capital all appear in the first 26 pages. It seems that, at least among kindle readers, most people didn’t make it past the introduction. It appears that people buy the book to back up the views they already hold.

David thinks that the huge interest in economic inequality in general and the wealth of the 1% in particular was sparked in the 1990s by politicians, including Al Gore, and picked up by journalists like Sylvia Nasar, before influencing the economics debate. Piketty has been able to ride this wave of public interest at what appears to be its crest.

David distinguishes between inequality of wealth, inequality of income, and inequality of power. Income inequality is the difference in the amount of income we each take in in wages, interest, dividends, and government transfers (e.g. welfare or social security payments), the four main sources of income for most people. Wealth should ideally include the total value of a person’s assets in addition to the stream of income he is likely to earn in the future, though this stream is more often ignored in wealth statistics. Wealth inequality is not the same as income inequality. Critically, since people earn variable income throughout their lives, income inequality doesn’t capture what we think of as the gap between “rich” and “poor.” Retired people who own two-million-dollar homes might have low incomes, but they certainly aren’t poor. Or, to use an example that’s relevant to myself, as a PhD student my income probably sits in the bottom quintile, and yet I can expect a much higher income after I graduate.

The major factor in both income inequality and wealth inequality (measured by current assets and not expected earnings) is age. Teenagers earn little or nothing, but they grow into adults and gain skills and education, their incomes rise, and they gain wealth through savings. Even if everyone had the same lifetime earnings, there would still be significant inequality in any given year since some people would be young low-earners, while others would be older, wealthier high-earners. And since the older people would have had the chance to accumulate wealth over a lifetime, they would have twenty times the wealth of their younger counterparts.

While there is a correlation between wealth and power, that correlation is by no means perfect. David gives the example of Bill Gates who discovered the hard way that when you have too little political influence, it can be costly. Gates was hit with a long and costly antitrust suit, after which he greatly expanded his lobbying efforts; he had learned his lesson. David agrees with Joseph Stiglitz’ argument, to some extent, that large accumulations of wealth are the result of rent seeking. Local governments restrict the building of new homes and developments that could expand the supply of housing. Thus, they keep real estate prices artificially high to the benefit of those who already own their homes. This is an example of successful rent seeking by homeowners to the detriment of non-homeowners. However, while Stiglitz would argue that this justifies a higher tax rate on the wealthy, David prefers the more direct solution of simply reducing or removing these restrictions.

The following are also mentioned in this episode:

Download this episode.

Subscribe to Economics Detective Radio on iTunes or Stitcher.

The post Income and Wealth Inequality with David R. Henderson appeared first on The Economics Detective.